Contextualism and closure

Authors

  • Nicholas D. Smith Lewis and Clark College

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.21638/spbu17.2020.207

Abstract

Skepticism confronts us with a paradox (sometimes known as “the skeptical trilemma”), a version of which follows: (1) I know that I am working on a computer right now; (2) I know that knowing that I am working on a computer right now logically implies that I am not being deceived or manipulated in the way that skeptical hypotheses imagine. (This implication is called “closure under known logical implication”); (3) I do not or cannot know that I am not being deceived or manipulated in the way skeptical hypotheses imagine. The paradox of skepticism is that these three statements are logically incompatible. A relatively new movement in epistemology called contextualism proposes that we can accept all three of the claims in the trilemma, by recognizing that they are not all true within the same epistemic context. Briefly, contextualists claim that we can know in ordinary contexts, but cannot know that we are not being deceived or manipulated in a skeptical scenario, but the latter fact is true in a different epistemic context than the ordinary knowledge that we might have. Closure under known logical implication will remain true, but only insofar as the implications involved are alternatives that belong to the same epistemic context as the original knowledge claim. In this paper, I claim that contextualism’s account of how epistemological contexts change, together with its acceptance of closure, is implausible.

Keywords:

epistemology, knowledge, closure, contextualism, fallibilism, logical implication, skepticism

Downloads

Download data is not yet available.
 

References

References

1. Cohen, S. (1988), How to Be a Fallibilist, in Tomberlin, J. (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, vol. 2, pp. 91–123.

2. Lehrer, K. (2000), Theory of Knowledge, Boulder, Colorado: Westview Press.

3. Cohen, S. (2000), Contextualism and Skepticism, in Sosa, E. and Villanueva, E. (eds), Skepticism, Boston: Blackwell.

4. Cohen, S. (2001), Contextualism Defended: Comments on Richard Feldman’s ‘Skeptical Problems, Contextualist Solutions’, Philosophical Studies, vol. 103, no. 1, pp. 87–98.

5. Lewis, D. (1996), Elusive Knowledge, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, vol. 74, no. 4, pp. 549–567.

6. DeRose, K. (1992), Contextualism and Knowledge Attribution, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, vol. 52, no. 4, pp. 913–929.

7. DeRose, K. (1995), Solving the Skeptical Problem, The Philosophical Review, vol. 104, no. 1, pp. 1–52.

8. DeRose, K. (2002), Assertion, Knowledge, and Context, The Philosophical Review, vol. 111, no. 2, pp. 167–203.

9. Cohen, S. (1999), Contextualism, Skepticism, and the Structure of Reasons, Philosophical Perspectives, vol. 13, pp. 58–89.

10. Cohen, S. (1986), Knowledge and Context, The Journal of Philosophy, vol. 83, pp. 574–583.

11. Alexander, J. and Weinberg, J. M. (2007), Analytic Epistemology and Experimental Philosophy, Philosophy Compass, no. 2, vol. 1, pp. 56–80

Published

2020-06-30

How to Cite

Smith, N. D. (2020). Contextualism and closure. Vestnik of Saint Petersburg University. Philosophy and Conflict Studies, 36(2), 291–299. https://doi.org/10.21638/spbu17.2020.207